Better Than “Best Interests:” Ensuring Children’s Wellbeing
November 4, 2023Feature Article(Source)
Children must be protected. This obligation animates much of United States political landscape. In the name of their protection, policymakers have pursued laws limiting not only children’s access to healthcare and to information, but also adults’ access to healthcare and to information. In this way, children’s protection is often instrumentalized to repress the autonomy of all. In decisions regarding children, courts are guided by a policy of protecting children’s “best interests”; but does this policy unduly interfere with the freedoms of adults? And more importantly: is it effective in protecting children?
Child maltreatment is an ongoing and pervasive problem. Over 1/3 of children experience a child protective services investigation before they turn 18 and an approximated 600,000 children were maltreated in just 2021, a prevalence rate that had not changed much in the prior 7 years. Children are maltreated both at the hands of family members and state-assigned custodians.
Not only harmed by direct mistreatment, children are also structurally disenfranchised. Kicked out of public spaces, facing barriers to transit, suffering from decaying school budgets, and with only a limited legal voice of their own, children as a political group are amongst the most marginalized. The United States especially lags behind other major developed countries in protecting children’s rights. How can policy simultaneously protect the child’s interest in safety and demarginalization and the adult’s interest in freedom and autonomy? In this article, I argue that bolstering children’s rights against the state effectively addresses each of these interests.
The Law
Parents have a “fundamental” right to direct the upbringing of their children, which courts have interpreted to mean that parents have a virtually unreviewable decision-making power over their children’s lives. The federal or state governments may only interfere with a parent’s decision when there is a “compelling state interest” to do so – such as protecting the child from harm.
Omnipresent in family law is the “best interests of the child” standard. This doctrine is relevant when the court assumes decision-making power over a child’s life, such as during custody determinations. Otherwise, courts presume that a parent’s decision for their child is in the child’s best interest, only rebutting that presumption through a finding of parental unfitness. When “best interests” doctrine is used, it works within a framework of child welfare, not child rights. Children deemed “mature” gain access to more autonomy and rights but are still largely covered by a child welfare framework. Thus, the doctrine creates a fault-based system that awards control of children to an entity deemed fit.
The Problem
“Best interests” doctrine fails to protect the liberty interests of parents or the safety of children because it is a substitution for parental discretion rather than an actual balancing of interests in tension. The doctrine fails to protect parental interests in the sense that it too quickly interferes with a parent’s ability to advocate for their children in the case of undervalued parents. It fails to protect children’s interests by assuming parents effectively advocate for their children; it has no tool for better aligning that advocacy with the child’s wants or needs aside from preventing maltreatment. Conversely, when the doctrine assumes parents cannot or will not advocate for their children, it does not provide a useful alternative – instead reassigning the child a new advocate in the form of the state or a foster custodian.
Even if “best interests” was expanded to review any parental decision outside of a fault-based framework, it would still be ineffective in producing child safety because the doctrine is aimed less at protecting the interests of children and more at protecting the interests the state has in children. For example, community integration is deemed to be in a child’s best interest when the child comes from a Christian or middle-class household, but not if the child comes from a working-class urban community or a family deemed neglectful. Children’s interests do not explain these different outcomes; community integration has the same effect upon the child regardless of how conventionally “good” the community is. The interests of savior-adopters – a more influential interest group than the families from which adoptees hail – do explain the difference, as foster children from “tragic” homes make better adoptees if they are unencumbered by ongoing connections to their past.
A Solution
A system based on rights rather than welfare would continue to provide a floor of treatment for children without relying on the assumption of a willing and able advocate existing. By reassigning power from the state to the child to represent the child’s interests, the involvement of third-party interests is diminished in decisions regarding children’s lives while creating a tool to challenge poor parental care outside of a fault-based paradigm. And incidentally, by using a rights-based system, children’s dignity and personhood is affirmed, reducing the risk of adults being stripped of autonomy or dignity through comparison to children.
This solution moves child welfare policy in the right direction, but it alone does not completely resolve the issue of children’s safety and demarginalization. A rights-based system does not necessitate and likely would not take the form of affirmative rights. Without an obligation to intervene at the individual level, cases of severe maltreatment could continue regardless of a rights-based or interest-based system. Furthermore, the issue of competing rights is not yet resolved in US jurisprudence. Where a child’s rights are in direct conflict with their parent’s, a court would likely rule in favor of the parent, limiting the efficacy of the system to challenge non-maltreatment harm. To fully address a child’s interests in wellbeing, broad human rights reform will be needed.
Suggested Citation: Alecia Robins, Better Than “Best Interests:” Ensuring Children’s Wellbeing, Cornell J.L. & Pub. Pol’y, The Issue Spotter (November 4, 2023), https://live-journal-of-law-and-public-policy.pantheonsite.io/better-than-best-interests-ensuring-childrens-wellbeing/.
You may also like
- November 2024
- October 2024
- April 2024
- March 2024
- February 2024
- November 2023
- October 2023
- April 2023
- March 2023
- February 2023
- January 2023
- December 2022
- November 2022
- October 2022
- May 2022
- April 2022
- March 2022
- February 2022
- January 2022
- December 2021
- November 2021
- October 2021
- May 2021
- April 2021
- March 2021
- February 2021
- January 2021
- November 2020
- October 2020
- September 2020
- August 2020
- July 2020
- June 2020
- May 2020
- April 2020
- March 2020
- February 2020
- January 2020
- November 2019
- October 2019
- September 2019
- April 2019
- February 2019
- December 2018
- November 2018
- October 2018
- September 2018
- March 2018
- February 2018
- January 2018
- December 2017
- November 2017
- October 2017
- September 2017
- May 2017
- April 2017
- March 2017
- February 2017
- December 2016
- November 2016
- October 2016
- April 2016
- March 2016
- February 2016
- January 2016
- December 2015
- November 2015
- October 2015
- June 2015
- May 2015
- April 2015
- March 2015
- February 2015
- January 2015
- December 2014
- November 2014
- October 2014
- August 2014
- March 2014
- February 2014
- January 2014
- December 2013
- November 2013
- October 2013
- September 2013
- May 2013
- April 2013
- March 2013
- February 2013
- January 2013
- December 2012
- November 2012
- October 2012
- September 2012
- June 2012
- April 2012
- March 2012
- February 2012
- January 2012
- December 2011
- November 2011
- October 2011
- September 2011
- August 2011
- April 2011
- March 2011
- November 2010
- October 2010
- September 2010