The Limits of Conscientious Objection
October 11, 2011Professor Blogs ArticleProfessor Michael Dorf, Robert S. Stevens Professor of Law, is a distinguished member of our renowned faculty at Cornell Law School. He has written dozens of articles on Constitutional law and related subjects. After law school, Professor Dorf clerked for Judge Stephen Reinhardt of the United States Court of Appeals for the Ninth Circuit and later for Justice Kennedy of the of the Supreme Court. In this post, Professor Dorf explores why conscientious objectors to gay marriage are not given the same deference as other conscientious objectors such as Quakers opposed to serving in the military. He also discusses what level of participation,in an act considered immoral, is required by a conscientious objector for an exemption to be recognized by the law.
By Prof. Michael C. Dorf.
A local controversy raises some interesting questions about the proper scope of rights to conscientious objection. Rose Marie Belforti is the Clerk of the Town of Ledyard in nearby Cayuga County. Citing her religious-based moral objections, she recently refused to issue a marriage license to a same-sex couple, although she agreed (perhaps after some discussion) to delegate the job of issuing marriage licenses to the deputy clerk, who has no objection to issuing licenses to same-sex couples. According to the news story, the two women who sought the marriage license are considering possible litigation.
In this post, I want to consider two questions: 1) What distinctions should the law draw among the substantive grounds for conscientious objection? and 2) What counts as participation in activity deemed morally objectionable.
1) Substantive Grounds
For people like me who favor same-sex marriage, it may be hard to sympathize with Ms. Belforti. The fact that she finds same-sex marriage immoral strikes me as bigotry, not much ameliorated by the fact that Belforti, like other opponents of same-sex marriage, invokes religious scruples. After all, Scriptural authority can be, and has been, invoked to support slavery, collective punishment, subjugation of women, and other practices that people like Ms. Belforti do not now attempt to rationalize. Thus, we think that Belforti and her religious community have made a conscious choice to oppose same-sex marriage, even while other religious communities using the same holy books have made a choice to welcome gays and lesbians as full equals.
To be sure, the same could be said for other conscientious objector claims. Quakers read the same Bible as other Protestant sects, but end up as pacifists. Why then, does Belforti’s claim seem substantively less worthy than that of a Quaker who refuses to take up arms? A big part of the answer is that the Quaker’s pacificism is not tantamount to the view that some members of the community are less valuable than others, while that is a fair implication of the anti-same-sex-marriage view. Just as we would not be comfortable recognizing aright of a Town Clerk to decline to issue marriage licenses to interracial couples, so too here, the asserted right to conscientious objection is weakened by the fact that it appears to be part of a zero-sum game: Recognition of Belforti’s claim undermines the equality of marriage of same-sex couples.
Yet seen in wide enough angle, any conscientious claim can be seen as condemning some other people. The Quaker who refuses to fight could be understood to be insulting people who have different scruples. A vegan Town Clerk who objected to issuing hunting and fishing licenses on grounds that such activities are unethical could be understood to be making a statement about people who hunt and fish. Etc.
The difference between the Quaker and the vegan, on the one hand, and Ms. Belforti, on the other, is that the Quaker and the vegan make tacit statements (if at all) about members of the majority. The vast majority of people who think war not categorically immoral and consume animal products are not seriously threatened by the fact that a few of us oddballs hold views that regard their conduct as unethical. By contrast, gays and lesbians are a persecuted minority, and so the recognition of conscientious objector rights to denigrate them stings much more sharply.
2) Participation
Even if we assume that there ought to be circumstances in which conscientious objection to same-sex marriage should be recognized, there is an additional worry in the Belforti case. When the law recognizes exemptions for conscientious objectors, it typically does so for people who do not want to participate in acts they regard as immoral. For example, conscientious objector laws protect people from serving in the armed forces, from performing abortions, and from having to officiate at same-sex marriages (as in New York’s Marriage Equality Act itself).
Such laws do not protect people against indirectly supporting practices with which people disagree, even if they strongly disagree on moral and religious grounds. Quakers must pay taxes that support wars, just as my taxes go to subsidies for the animal exploitation industries, despite my desire not to participate in them.
Nor is it feasible to imagine that we could exempt everyone with a conscientious objection to some practice from even the remotest sort of participation in that practice. Administration of the tax code would be enormously complicated were we to allow checkoffs for particular budget items. And the problem does not end with taxes. A postal employee might object to delivering an envelope containing a marriage license to a same-sex couple or even to delivering mail containing promotional material for political candidates she opposes.
Where does a town clerk fall on the spectrum between objecting to fighting in a war and objecting to delivering mail for causes with which one disagrees? I’m inclined to think that it comes closer to the latter position, and thus that the government could legitimately enforce a rule that says that if you want to be a town clerk, you have to issue marriage licenses to everyone who legally qualifies.
That said, I do think we can also recognize that for people like Ms. Belforti, that’s a real harm (albeit one that the law will not accommodate). People will feel uncomfortable with a level of participation in what they regard as evil at some point below the threshold that the law can recognize for conscientious objector status.
For me personally, that point was driven home twenty years ago when, as a law clerk at the Supreme Court, I occasionally had to sign orders denying an application for a stay of execution, knowing that this was the last step before a person would be executed. Of course, it wasn’t my decision to deny the stay. I wasn’t even signing on my own behalf. (The last legal action often takes place in the wee hours of the morning, when only law clerks are left in the building, with the final authority coming via telephone call with the relevant Circuit Justice.) But still, I experienced the signing of my initials as a form of participation in capital punishment. So, even though I do not share her values, and even though I think she should be denied the power to opt out, I do sympathize with Ms. Belforti.
You may also like
2 comments
- November 2024
- October 2024
- April 2024
- March 2024
- February 2024
- November 2023
- October 2023
- April 2023
- March 2023
- February 2023
- January 2023
- December 2022
- November 2022
- October 2022
- May 2022
- April 2022
- March 2022
- February 2022
- January 2022
- December 2021
- November 2021
- October 2021
- May 2021
- April 2021
- March 2021
- February 2021
- January 2021
- November 2020
- October 2020
- September 2020
- August 2020
- July 2020
- June 2020
- May 2020
- April 2020
- March 2020
- February 2020
- January 2020
- November 2019
- October 2019
- September 2019
- April 2019
- February 2019
- December 2018
- November 2018
- October 2018
- September 2018
- March 2018
- February 2018
- January 2018
- December 2017
- November 2017
- October 2017
- September 2017
- May 2017
- April 2017
- March 2017
- February 2017
- December 2016
- November 2016
- October 2016
- April 2016
- March 2016
- February 2016
- January 2016
- December 2015
- November 2015
- October 2015
- June 2015
- May 2015
- April 2015
- March 2015
- February 2015
- January 2015
- December 2014
- November 2014
- October 2014
- August 2014
- March 2014
- February 2014
- January 2014
- December 2013
- November 2013
- October 2013
- September 2013
- May 2013
- April 2013
- March 2013
- February 2013
- January 2013
- December 2012
- November 2012
- October 2012
- September 2012
- June 2012
- April 2012
- March 2012
- February 2012
- January 2012
- December 2011
- November 2011
- October 2011
- September 2011
- August 2011
- April 2011
- March 2011
- November 2010
- October 2010
- September 2010
Professor Dorf makes several great points. When conscientious objectors fall within the minority, it is much easier to understand their point of view. However, when as here, the conscientious objectors are the majority opposing actions of the minority, concerns should be raised. Our country has a dark history of the majority imposing their will on the minority, and when such actions become evident, it will be to all our benefits to ensure that the majority’s actions are deeply scrutinized.
The law is willing to recognize the right of conscientious objectors to refuse to participate in acts they consider immoral. How much participation is required for the law to recognize an exemption? As Professor Dorf points out, the law does not protect indirect participation by conscientious objectors. A mailman does not have the discretion to choose the mail he delivers. Likewise, an elected town clerk should not have the discretion on whether to issue marriage certificates to same-sex couples. As an elected official, her responsibility is to ensure that the affairs of all her constituents are catered to and not just the people she approves of. I do not sympathize with Ms. Belforti’s objections. If her actions in refusing to issue marriage certificate to same-sex couples are recognized by the law, the country will have taken a backward step in Civil Rights. If the law recognizes her objection not to issue certificates to same-sex couples, what will stop the next person from refusing to issue certificates to interracial couples?
Ms. Belforti’s refusal to perform her job is somewhat troubling. While I understand entirely that she may feel a religious revulsion to licensing same-sex couples, I’m not sure if that’s entirely a justification for the system to bend to her will. If religious beliefs suddenly exempt state workers from their duties, then not only will the state be crippled by every single religious person it hires, but it will simultaneously create an incentive for local religious groups to flood hiring offices with their devotees in order to inhibit state behavior.
This could be taken to a logical extreme. Imagine a hypothetical county filled with 99.9% devout Christians against same-sex marriage. The other .1% is (conveniently) filled with same-sex couples. In this scenario, presuming the 99.9% have filled all of the state positions, then even if same-sex marriage was legal in that state, the .1% would be out of luck and would be forced to move or to suffer the limitations. Dominant religions would craft the boundaries of the state, and that’s scary.
I hate to say this, but if Ms. Belforti has a problem with the duties she’s been assigned, she should resign. If Ms. Belforti truly believes in her cause, she should be willing to do so. Like Randy says, a mailman does not have the discretion to choose the mail he delivers, and similarly, Ms. Belforti should not have the option of choosing which laws she enforces.